HOW SOME PEOPLE ADJUST
77. Not everyone in industrial-technological
society suffers from psychological problems. Some people even profess to
be quite satisfied with society as it is. We now discuss some of the reasons
why people differ so greatly in their response to modern society.
78. First, there doubtless
are differences in the strength of the drive for power. Individuals with
a weak drive for power may have relatively little need to go through the
power process, or at least relatively little need for autonomy in the power
process. These are docile types who would have been happy as plantation
darkies in the Old South. (We don't mean to sneer at "plantation darkies"
of the Old South. To their credit, most of the slaves were NOT content
with their servitude. We do snee r at people who ARE content with servitude.)
79. Some people may have
some exceptional drive, in pursuing which they satisfy their need for the
power process. For example, those who have an unusually strong drive for
social status may spend their whole lives climbing the status ladder without
ev er getting bored with that game.
80. People vary in their
susceptibility to advertising and marketing techniques. Some people are
so susceptible that, even if they make a great deal of money, they cannot
satisfy their constant craving for the shiny new toys that the marketing
industry dangles before their eyes. So they always feel hard-pressed financially
even if their income is large, and their cravings are frustrated.
81. Some people have low
susceptibility to advertising and marketing techniques. These are the people
who aren't interested in money. Material acquisition does not serve their
need for the power process.
82. People who have medium
susceptibility to advertising and marketing techniques are able to earn
enough money to satisfy their craving for goods and services, but only
at the cost of serious effort (putting in overtime, taking a second job,
earning p romotions, etc.) Thus material acquisition serves their need
for the power process. But it does not necessarily follow that their need
is fully satisfied. They may have insufficient autonomy in the power process
(their work may consist of following orders ) and some of their drives
may be frustrated (e.g., security, aggression). (We are guilty of oversimplification
in paragraphs 80-82 because we have assumed that the desire for material
acquisition is entirely a creation of the advertising and marketing in
dustry. Of course it's not that simple.
83. Some people partly satisfy
their need for power by identifying themselves with a powerful organization
or mass movement. An individual lacking goals or power joins a movement
or an organization, adopts its goals as his own, then works toward these
goals. When some of the goals are attained, the individual, even though
his personal efforts have played only an insignificant part in the attainment
of the goals, feels (through his identification with the movement or organization)
as if he had gone thro ugh the power process. This phenomenon was exploited
by the fascists, nazis and communists. Our society uses it, too, though
less crudely. Example: Manuel Noriega was an irritant to the U.S. (goal:
punish Noriega). The U.S. invaded Panama (effort) and pun ished Noriega
(attainment of goal). The U.S. went through the power process and many
Americans, because of their identification with the U.S., experienced the
power process vicariously. Hence the widespread public approval of the
Panama invasion; it gave people a sense of power. [15] We see the same
phenomenon in armies, corporations, political parties, humanitarian organizations,
religious or ideological movements. In particular, leftist movements tend
to attract people who are seeking to satisfy their n eed for power. But
for most people identification with a large organization or a mass movement
does not fully satisfy the need for power.
84. Another way in which
people satisfy their need for the power process is through surrogate activities.
As we explained in paragraphs 38-40, a surrogate activity that is directed
toward an artificial goal that the individual pursues for the sake of t
he "fulfillment" that he gets from pursuing the goal, not because he needs
to attain the goal itself. For instance, there is no practical motive for
building enormous muscles, hitting a little ball into a hole or acquiring
a complete series of postage sta mps. Yet many people in our society devote
themselves with passion to bodybuilding, golf or stamp collecting. Some
people are more "other-directed" than others, and therefore will more readily
attack importance to a surrogate activity simply because the p eople around
them treat it as important or because society tells them it is important.
That is why some people get very serious about essentially trivial activities
such as sports, or bridge, or chess, or arcane scholarly pursuits, whereas
others who are more clear-sighted never see these things as anything but
the surrogate activities that they are, and consequently never attach enough
importance to them to satisfy their need for the power process in that
way. It only remains to point out that in many ca ses a person's way of
earning a living is also a surrogate activity. Not a PURE surrogate activity,
since part of the motive for the activity is to gain the physical necessities
and (for some people) social status and the luxuries that advertising makes
t hem want. But many people put into their work far more effort than is
necessary to earn whatever money and status they require, and this extra
effort constitutes a surrogate activity. This extra effort, together with
the emotional investment that accompan ies it, is one of the most potent
forces acting toward the continual development and perfecting of the system,
with negative consequences for individual freedom (see paragraph 131).
Especially, for the most creative scientists and engineers, work tends
to be largely a surrogate activity. This point is so important that is
deserves a separate discussion, which we shall give in a moment (paragraphs
87-92).
85. In this section we have
explained how many people in modern society do satisfy their need for the
power process to a greater or lesser extent. But we think that for the
majority of people the need for the power process is not fully satisfied.
In th e first place, those who have an insatiable drive for status, or
who get firmly "hooked" or a surrogate activity, or who identify strongly
enough with a movement or organization to satisfy their need for power
in that way, are exceptional personalities. O thers are not fully satisfied
with surrogate activities or by identification with an organization (see
paragraphs 41, 64). In the second place, too much control is imposed by
the system through explicit regulation or through socialization, which
results i n a deficiency of autonomy, and in frustration due to the impossibility
of attaining certain goals and the necessity of restraining too many impulses.
86. But even if most people
in industrial-technological society were well satisfied, we (FC) would
still be opposed to that form of society, because (among other reasons)
we consider it demeaning to fulfill one's need for the power process through
surr ogate activities or through identification with an organization, rather
then through pursuit of real goals.
THE MOTIVES OF SCIENTISTS
87. Science and technology
provide the most important examples of surrogate activities. Some scientists
claim that they are motivated by "curiosity," that notion is simply absurd.
Most scientists work on highly specialized problem that are not the obje
ct of any normal curiosity. For example, is an astronomer, a mathematician
or an entomologist curious about the properties of isopropyltrimethylmethane?
Of course not. Only a chemist is curious about such a thing, and he is
curious about it only because c hemistry is his surrogate activity. Is
the chemist curious about the appropriate classification of a new species
of beetle? No. That question is of interest only to the entomologist, and
he is interested in it only because entomology is his surrogate acti vity.
If the chemist and the entomologist had to exert themselves seriously to
obtain the physical necessities, and if that effort exercised their abilities
in an interesting way but in some nonscientific pursuit, then they couldn't
giver a damn about iso propyltrimethylmethane or the classification of
beetles. Suppose that lack of funds for postgraduate education had led
the chemist to become an insurance broker instead of a chemist. In that
case he would have been very interested in insurance matters but would
have cared nothing about isopropyltrimethylmethane. In any case it is not
normal to put into the satisfaction of mere curiosity the amount of time
and effort that scientists put into their work. The "curiosity" explanation
for the scientists' motiv e just doesn't stand up.
88. The "benefit of humanity"
explanation doesn't work any better. Some scientific work has no conceivable
relation to the welfare of the human race - most of archaeology or comparative
linguistics for example. Some other areas of science present obvio usly
dangerous possibilities. Yet scientists in these areas are just as enthusiastic
about their work as those who develop vaccines or study air pollution.
Consider the case of Dr. Edward Teller, who had an obvious emotional involvement
in promoting nucle ar power plants. Did this involvement stem from a desire
to benefit humanity? If so, then why didn't Dr. Teller get emotional about
other "humanitarian" causes? If he was such a humanitarian then why did
he help to develop the H-bomb? As with many other s cientific achievements,
it is very much open to question whether nuclear power plants actually
do benefit humanity. Does the cheap electricity outweigh the accumulating
waste and risk of accidents? Dr. Teller saw only one side of the question.
Clearly his emotional involvement with nuclear power arose not from a desire
to "benefit humanity" but from a personal fulfillment he got from his work
and from seeing it put to practical use.
89. The same is true of
scientists generally. With possible rare exceptions, their motive is neither
curiosity nor a desire to benefit humanity but the need to go through the
power process: to have a goal (a scientific problem to solve), to make
an eff ort (research) and to attain the goal (solution of the problem.)
Science is a surrogate activity because scientists work mainly for the
fulfillment they get out of the work itself.
90. Of course, it's not
that simple. Other motives do play a role for many scientists. Money and
status for example. Some scientists may be persons of the type who have
an insatiable drive for status (see paragraph 79) and this may provide
much of the motivation for their work. No doubt the majority of scientists,
like the majority of the general population, are more or less susceptible
to advertising and marketing techniques and need money to satisfy their
craving for goods and services. Thus science is not a PURE surrogate activity.
But it is in large part a surrogate activity.
91. Also, science and technology
constitute a mass power movement, and many scientists gratify their need
for power through identification with this mass movement (see paragraph
83).
92. Thus science marches
on blindly, without regard to the real welfare of the human race or to
any other standard, obedient only to the psychological needs of the scientists
and of the government officials and corporation executives who provide
the fu nds for research.
THE NATURE OF FREEDOM
93. We are going to argue that
industrial-technological society cannot be reformed in such a way as to
prevent it from progressively narrowing the sphere of human freedom. But
because "freedom" is a word that can be interpreted in many ways, we must
fi rst make clear what kind of freedom we are concerned with.
94. By "freedom" we mean
the opportunity to go through the power process, with real goals not the
artificial goals of surrogate activities, and without interference, manipulation
or supervision from anyone, especially from any large organization. Freed
om means being in control (either as an individual or as a member of a
SMALL group) of the life-and-death issues of one's existence; food, clothing,
shelter and defense against whatever threats there may be in one's environment.
Freedom means having power ; not the power to control other people but
the power to control the circumstances of one's own life. One does not
have freedom if anyone else (especially a large organization) has power
over one, no matter how benevolently, tolerantly and permissively th at
power may be exercised. It is important not to confuse freedom with mere
permissiveness (see paragraph 72).
95. It is said that we live
in a free society because we have a certain number of constitutionally
guaranteed rights. But these are not as important as they seem. The degree
of personal freedom that exists in a society is determined more by the
economi c and technological structure of the society than by its laws or
its form of government. [16] Most of the Indian nations of New England
were monarchies, and many of the cities of the Italian Renaissance were
controlled by dictators. But in reading about t hese societies one gets
the impression that they allowed far more personal freedom than out society
does. In part this was because they lacked efficient mechanisms for enforcing
the ruler's will: There were no modern, well-organized police forces, no
rapi d long-distance communications, no surveillance cameras, no dossiers
of information about the lives of average citizens. Hence it was relatively
easy to evade control.
96. As for our constitutional
rights, consider for example that of freedom of the press. We certainly
don't mean to knock that right: it is very important tool for limiting
concentration of political power and for keeping those who do have political
po wer in line by publicly exposing any misbehavior on their part. But
freedom of the press is of very little use to the average citizen as an
individual. The mass media are mostly under the control of large organizations
that are integrated into the system. Anyone who has a little money can
have something printed, or can distribute it on the Internet or in some
such way, but what he has to say will be swamped by the vast volume of
material put out by the media, hence it will have no practical effect.
To mak e an impression on society with words is therefore almost impossible
for most individuals and small groups. Take us (FC) for example. If we
had never done anything violent and had submitted the present writings
to a publisher, they probably would not have been accepted. If they had
been accepted and published, they probably would not have attracted many
readers, because it's more fun to watch the entertainment put out by the
media than to read a sober essay. Even if these writings had had many readers,
mo st of these readers would soon have forgotten what they had read as
their minds were flooded by the mass of material to which the media expose
them. In order to get our message before the public with some chance of
making a lasting impression, we've had t o kill people.
97. Constitutional rights
are useful up to a point, but they do not serve to guarantee much more
than what could be called the bourgeois conception of freedom. According
to the bourgeois conception, a "free" man is essentially an element of
a social ma chine and has only a certain set of prescribed and delimited
freedoms; freedoms that are designed to serve the needs of the social machine
more than those of the individual. Thus the bourgeois's "free" man has
economic freedom because that promotes growth and progress; he has freedom
of the press because public criticism restrains misbehavior by political
leaders; he has a rights to a fair trial because imprisonment at the whim
of the powerful would be bad for the system. This was clearly the attitude
of Simon Bolivar. To him, people deserved liberty only if they used it
to promote progress (progress as conceived by the bourgeois). Other bourgeois
thinkers have taken a similar view of freedom as a mere means to collective
ends. Chester C. Tan, "Chinese Po litical Thought in the Twentieth Century,"
page 202, explains the philosophy of the Kuomintang leader Hu Han-min:
"An individual is granted rights because he is a member of society and
his community life requires such rights. By community Hu meant the who
le society of the nation." And on page 259 Tan states that according to
Carsum Chang (Chang Chun-mai, head of the State Socialist Party in China)
freedom had to be used in the interest of the state and of the people as
a whole. But what kind of freedom do es one have if one can use it only
as someone else prescribes? FC's conception of freedom is not that of Bolivar,
Hu, Chang or other bourgeois theorists. The trouble with such theorists
is that they have made the development and application of social theo ries
their surrogate activity. Consequently the theories are designed to serve
the needs of the theorists more than the needs of any people who may be
unlucky enough to live in a society on which the theories are imposed.
98. One more point to be
made in this section: It should not be assumed that a person has enough
freedom just because he SAYS he has enough. Freedom is restricted in part
by psychological control of which people are unconscious, and moreover
many peopl e's ideas of what constitutes freedom are governed more by social
convention than by their real needs. For example, it's likely that many
leftists of the oversocialized type would say that most people, including
themselves are socialized too little rather than too much, yet the oversocialized
leftist pays a heavy psychological price for his high level of socialization.
SOME PRINCIPLES OF HISTORY
99. Think of history as being
the sum of two components: an erratic component that consists of unpredictable
events that follow no discernible pattern, and a regular component that
consists of long-term historical trends. Here we are concerned with the
long-term trends.
100. FIRST PRINCIPLE. If
a SMALL change is made that affects a long-term historical trend, then
the effect of that change will almost always be transitory - the trend
will soon revert to its original state. (Example: A reform movement designed
to clean up political corruption in a society rarely has more than a short-term
effect; sooner or later the reformers relax and corruption creeps back
in. The level of political corruption in a given society tends to remain
constant, or to change only slowly with the evolution of the society. Normally,
a political cleanup will be permanent only if accompanied by widespread
social changes; a SMALL change in the society won't be enough.) If a small
change in a long-term historical trend appears to be permanent, it is only
because the change acts in the direction in which the trend is already
moving, so that the trend is not altered but only pushed a step ahead.
101. The first principle
is almost a tautology. If a trend were not stable with respect to small
changes, it would wander at random rather than following a definite direction;
in other words it would not be a long-term trend at all.
102. SECOND PRINCIPLE. If
a change is made that is sufficiently large to alter permanently a long-term
historical trend, than it will alter the society as a whole. In other words,
a society is a system in which all parts are interrelated, and you can't
permanently change any important part without change all the other parts
as well.
103. THIRD PRINCIPLE. If
a change is made that is large enough to alter permanently a long-term
trend, then the consequences for the society as a whole cannot be predicted
in advance. (Unless various other societies have passed through the same
change and have all experienced the same consequences, in which case one
can predict on empirical grounds that another society that passes through
the same change will be like to experience similar consequences.)
104. FOURTH PRINCIPLE. A
new kind of society cannot be designed on paper. That is, you cannot plan
out a new form of society in advance, then set it up and expect it to function
as it was designed to.
105. The third and fourth
principles result from the complexity of human societies. A change in human
behavior will affect the economy of a society and its physical environment;
the economy will affect the environment and vice versa, and the changes
in the economy and the environment will affect human behavior in complex,
unpredictable ways; and so forth. The network of causes and effects is
far too complex to be untangled and understood.
106. FIFTH PRINCIPLE. People
do not consciously and rationally choose the form of their society. Societies
develop through processes of social evolution that are not under rational
human control.
107. The fifth principle
is a consequence of the other four.
108. To illustrate: By the
first principle, generally speaking an attempt at social reform either
acts in the direction in which the society is developing anyway (so that
it merely accelerates a change that would have occurred in any case) or
else it o nly has a transitory effect, so that the society soon slips back
into its old groove. To make a lasting change in the direction of development
of any important aspect of a society, reform is insufficient and revolution
is required. (A revolution does not necessarily involve an armed uprising
or the overthrow of a government.) By the second principle, a revolution
never changes only one aspect of a society; and by the third principle
changes occur that were never expected or desired by the revolutionaries.
By the fourth principle, when revolutionaries or utopians set up a new
kind of society, it never works out as planned.
109. The American Revolution
does not provide a counterexample. The American "Revolution" was not a
revolution in our sense of the word, but a war of independence followed
by a rather far-reaching political reform. The Founding Fathers did not
change t he direction of development of American society, nor did they
aspire to do so. They only freed the development of American society from
the retarding effect of British rule. Their political reform did not change
any basic trend, but only pushed American p olitical culture along its
natural direction of development. British society, of which American society
was an off-shoot, had been moving for a long time in the direction of representative
democracy. And prior to the War of Independence the Americans were already
practicing a significant degree of representative democracy in the colonial
assemblies. The political system established by the Constitution was modeled
on the British system and on the colonial assemblies. With major alteration,
to be sure - the re is no doubt that the Founding Fathers took a very important
step. But it was a step along the road the English-speaking world was already
traveling. The proof is that Britain and all of its colonies that were
populated predominantly by people of Britis h descent ended up with systems
of representative democracy essentially similar to that of the United States.
If the Founding Fathers had lost their nerve and declined to sign the Declaration
of Independence, our way of life today would not have been sign ificantly
different. Maybe we would have had somewhat closer ties to Britain, and
would have had a Parliament and Prime Minister instead of a Congress and
President. No big deal. Thus the American Revolution provides not a counterexample
to our principles but a good illustration of them.
110. Still, one has to use
common sense in applying the principles. They are expressed in imprecise
language that allows latitude for interpretation, and exceptions to them
can be found. So we present these principles not as inviolable laws but
as rule s of thumb, or guides to thinking, that may provide a partial antidote
to naive ideas about the future of society. The principles should be borne
constantly in mind, and whenever one reaches a conclusion that conflicts
with them one should carefully reexa mine one's thinking and retain the
conclusion only if one has good, solid reasons for doing so.
INDUSTRIAL-TECHNOLOGICAL SOCIETY
CANNOT BE REFORMED
111. The foregoing principles
help to show how hopelessly difficult it would be to reform the industrial
system in such a way as to prevent it from progressively narrowing our
sphere of freedom. There has been a consistent tendency, going back at
least to the Industrial Revolution for technology to strengthen the system
at a high cost in individual freedom and local autonomy. Hence any change
designed to protect freedom from technology would be contrary to a fundamental
trend in the development of our society.
Consequently, such a change
either would be a transitory one -- soon swamped by the tide of history
-- or, if large enough to be permanent would alter the nature of our whole
society. This by the first and second principles. Moreover, since society
wo uld be altered in a way that could not be predicted in advance (third
principle) there would be great risk. Changes large enough to make a lasting
difference in favor of freedom would not be initiated because it would
realized that they would gravely dis rupt the system. So any attempts at
reform would be too timid to be effective. Even if changes large enough
to make a lasting difference were initiated, they would be retracted when
their disruptive effects became apparent. Thus, permanent changes in fav
or of freedom could be brought about only by persons prepared to accept
radical, dangerous and unpredictable alteration of the entire system. In
other words, by revolutionaries, not reformers.
112. People anxious to rescue
freedom without sacrificing the supposed benefits of technology will suggest
naive schemes for some new form of society that would reconcile freedom
with technology. Apart from the fact that people who make suggestions sel
dom propose any practical means by which the new form of society could
be set up in the first place, it follows from the fourth principle that
even if the new form of society could be once established, it either would
collapse or would give results very d ifferent from those expected.
113. So even on very general
grounds it seems highly improbably that any way of changing society could
be found that would reconcile freedom with modern technology. In the next
few sections we will give more specific reasons for concluding that freedo
m and technological progress are incompatible.
RESTRICTION OF FREEDOM
IS UNAVOIDABLE IN INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY
114. As explained in paragraph
65-67, 70-73, modern man is strapped down by a network of rules and regulations,
and his fate depends on the actions of persons remote from him whose decisions
he cannot influence. This is not accidental or a result of t he arbitrariness
of arrogant bureaucrats. It is necessary and inevitable in any technologically
advanced society. The system HAS TO regulate human behavior closely in
order to function. At work, people have to do what they are told to do,
otherwise prod uction would be thrown into chaos. Bureaucracies HAVE TO
be run according to rigid rules. To allow any substantial personal discretion
to lower-level bureaucrats would disrupt the system and lead to charges
of unfairness due to differences in the way indi vidual bureaucrats exercised
their discretion. It is true that some restrictions on our freedom could
be eliminated, but GENERALLY SPEAKING the regulation of our lives by large
organizations is necessary for the functioning of industrial-technological
soc iety. The result is a sense of powerlessness on the part of the average
person. It may be, however, that formal regulations will tend increasingly
to be replaced by psychological tools that make us want to do what the
system requires of us. (Propaganda [1 4], educational techniques, "mental
health" programs, etc.)
115. The system HAS TO force
people to behave in ways that are increasingly remote from the natural
pattern of human behavior. For example, the system needs scientists, mathematicians
and engineers. It can't function without them. So heavy pressure is put
on children to excel in these fields. It isn't natural for an adolescent
human being to spend the bulk of his time sitting at a desk absorbed in
study. A normal adolescent wants to spend his time in active contact with
the real world. Among primitive peoples the things that children are trained
to do are in natural harmony with natural human impulses. Among the American
Indians, for example, boys were trained in active outdoor pursuits -- just
the sort of things that boys like. But in our society chil dren are pushed
into studying technical subjects, which most do grudgingly.
116. Because of the constant
pressure that the system exerts to modify human behavior, there is a gradual
increase in the number of people who cannot or will not adjust to soc iety's
requirements: welfare leeches, youth-gang members, cultists, anti-government
rebels, radical environmentalist saboteurs, dropouts and resisters of various
kinds.
117. In any technologically
advanced society the individual's fate MUST depend on decisions that he
personally cannot influence to any great extent. A technological society
cannot be broken down into small, autonomous communities, because production
depends on the cooperation of very large numbers of people and machines.
Such a society MUST be highly organized and decisions HAVE TO be made that
affect very large numbers of people. When a decision affects, say, a million
people, then each of the affected individuals has, on the average, only
a one-millionth share in making the decision. What usually happens in practice
is that decisions are made by public officials or corporation executives,
or by technical specialists, but even when the public votes on a decision
the number of voters ordinarily is too large for the vote of any one indi
vidual to be significant. [17] Thus most individuals are unable to influence
measurably the major decisions that affect their lives. Their is no conceivable
way to remedy this in a technologically advanced society. The system tries
to "solve" this proble m by using propaganda to make people WANT the decisions
that have been made for them, but even if this "solution" were completely
successful in making people feel better, it would be demeaning.
118 Conservatives and some
others advocate more "local autonomy." Local communities once did have
autonomy, but such autonomy becomes less and less possible as local communities
become more enmeshed with and dependent on large-scale systems like public
utilities, computer networks, highway systems, the mass communications
media, the modern health care system. Also operating against autonomy is
the fact that technology applied in one location often affects people at
other locations far away. Thus pesti cide or chemical use near a creek
may contaminate the water supply hundreds of miles downstream, and the
greenhouse effect affects the whole world.
119. The system does not
and cannot exist to satisfy human needs. Instead, it is human behavior
that has to be modified to fit the needs of the system. This has nothing
to do with the political or social ideology that may pretend to guide the
technolog ical system. It is the fault of technology, because the system
is guided not by ideology but by technical necessity. [18] Of course the
system does satisfy many human needs, but generally speaking it does this
only to the extent that it is to the advantag e of the system to do it.
It is the needs of the system that are paramount, not those of the human
being. For example, the system provides people with food because the system
couldn't function if everyone starved; it attends to people's psychological
need s whenever it can CONVENIENTLY do so, because it couldn't function
if too many people became depressed or rebellious. But the system, for
good, solid, practical reasons, must exert constant pressure on people
to mold their behavior to the needs of the sys tem. Too much waste accumulating?
The government, the media, the educational system, environmentalists, everyone
inundates us with a mass of propaganda about recycling. Need more technical
personnel? A chorus of voices exhorts kids to study science. No on e stops
to ask whether it is inhumane to force adolescents to spend the bulk of
their time studying subjects most of them hate. When skilled workers are
put out of a job by technical advances and have to undergo "retraining,"
no one asks whether it is hum iliating for them to be pushed around in
this way. It is simply taken for granted that everyone must bow to technical
necessity and for good reason: If human needs were put before technical
necessity there would be economic problems, unemployment, shortag es or
worse. The concept of "mental health" in our society is defined largely
by the extent to which an individual behaves in accord with the needs of
the system and does so without showing signs of stress.
120. Efforts to make room
for a sense of purpose and for autonomy within the system are no better
than a joke. For example, one company, instead of having each of its employees
assemble only one section of a catalogue, had each assemble a whole catalog
ue, and this was supposed to give them a sense of purpose and achievement.
Some companies have tried to give their employees more autonomy in their
work, but for practical reasons this usually can be done only to a very
limited extent, and in any case emp loyees are never given autonomy as
to ultimate goals -- their "autonomous" efforts can never be directed toward
goals that they select personally, but only toward their employer's goals,
such as the survival and growth of the company. Any company would so on
go out of business if it permitted its employees to act otherwise. Similarly,
in any enterprise within a socialist system, workers must direct their
efforts toward the goals of the enterprise, otherwise the enterprise will
not serve its purpose as part of the system. Once again, for purely technical
reasons it is not possible for most individuals or small groups to have
much autonomy in industrial society. Even the small-business owner commonly
has only limited autonomy. Apart from the necessity of gov ernment regulation,
he is restricted by the fact that he must fit into the economic system
and conform to its requirements. For instance, when someone develops a
new technology, the small-business person often has to use that technology
whether he wants t o or not, in order to remain competitive.
THE 'BAD' PARTS OF TECHNOLOGY
CANNOT BE SEPARATED FROM THE 'GOOD' PARTS
121. A further reason why
industrial society cannot be reformed in favor of freedom is that modern
technology is a unified system in which all parts are dependent on one
another. You can't get rid of the "bad" parts of technology and retain
only the "g ood" parts. Take modern medicine, for example. Progress in
medical science depends on progress in chemistry, physics, biology, computer
science and other fields. Advanced medical treatments require expensive,
high-tech equipment that can be made available only by a technologically
progressive, economically rich society. Clearly you can't have much progress
in medicine without the whole technological system and everything that
goes with it.
122. Even if medical progress
could be maintained without the rest of the technological system, it would
by itself bring certain evils. Suppose for example that a cure for diabetes
is discovered. People with a genetic tendency to diabetes will then be
able to survive and reproduce as well as anyone else. Natural selection
against genes for diabetes will cease and such genes will spread throughout
the population. (This may be occurring to some extent already, since diabetes,
while not curable, can be c ontrolled through the use of insulin.) The
same thing will happen with many other diseases susceptibility to which
is affected by genetic degradation of the population. The only solution
will be some sort of eugenics program or extensive genetic engineeri ng
of human beings, so that man in the future will no longer be a creation
of nature, or of chance, or of God (depending on your religious or philosophical
opinions), but a manufactured product.
123. If you think that big
government interferes in your life too much NOW, just wait till the government
starts regulating the genetic constitution of your children. Such regulation
will inevitably follow the introduction of genetic engineering of hum an
beings, because the consequences of unregulated genetic engineering would
be disastrous. [19]
124. The usual response
to such concerns is to talk about "medical ethics." But a code of ethics
would not serve to protect freedom in the face of medical progress; it
would only make matters worse. A code of ethics applicable to genetic engineering
wo uld be in effect a means of regulating the genetic constitution of human
beings. Somebody (probably the upper-middle class, mostly) would decide
that such and such applications of genetic engineering were "ethical" and
others were not, so that in effect t hey would be imposing their own values
on the genetic constitution of the population at large. Even if a code
of ethics were chosen on a completely democratic basis, the majority would
be imposing their own values on any minorities who might have a differ
ent idea of what constituted an "ethical" use of genetic engineering. The
only code of ethics that would truly protect freedom would be one that
prohibited ANY genetic engineering of human beings, and you can be sure
that no such code will ever be applied in a technological society. No code
that reduced genetic engineering to a minor role could stand up for long,
because the temptation presented by the immense power of biotechnology
would be irresistible, especially since to the majority of people many
of its applications will seem obviously and unequivocally good (eliminating
physical and mental diseases, giving people the abilities they need to
get along in today's world). Inevitably, genetic engineering will be used
extensively, but only in ways consis tent with the needs of the industrial-technological
system. [20]
TECHNOLOGY IS A MORE POWERFUL
SOCIAL FORCE THAN THE ASPIRATION FOR FREEDOM
125. It is not possible to
make a LASTING compromise between technology and freedom, because technology
is by far the more powerful social force and continually encroaches on
freedom through REPEATED compromises. Imagine the case of two neighbors,
each of whom at the outset owns the same amount of land, but one of whom
is more powerful than the other. The powerful one demands a piece of the
other's land. The weak one refuses. The powerful one says, "OK, let's compromise.
Give me half of what I asked." The weak one has little choice but to give
in. Some time later the powerful neighbor demands another piece of land,
again there is a compromise, and so forth. By forcing a long series of
compromises on the weaker man, the powerful one eventually gets all of
his land. So it goes in the conflict between technology and freedom.
126. Let us explain why
technology is a more powerful social force than the aspiration for freedom.
127. A technological advance
that appears not to threaten freedom often turns out to threaten freedom
often turns out to threaten it very seriously later on. For example, consider
motorized transport. A walking man formerly could go where he pleased,
g o at his own pace without observing any traffic regulations, and was
independent of technological support-systems. When motor vehicles were
introduced they appeared to increase man's freedom. They took no freedom
away from the walking man, no one had to h ave an automobile if he didn't
want one, and anyone who did choose to buy an automobile could travel much
faster than the walking man. But the introduction of motorized transport
soon changed society in such a way as to restrict greatly man's freedom
of l ocomotion. When automobiles became numerous, it became necessary to
regulate their use extensively. In a car, especially in densely populated
areas, one cannot just go where one likes at one's own pace one's movement
is governed by the flow of traffic and by various traffic laws. One is
tied down by various obligations: license requirements, driver test, renewing
registration, insurance, maintenance required for safety, monthly payments
on purchase price. Moreover, the use of motorized transport is no lon ger
optional. Since the introduction of motorized transport the arrangement
of our cities has changed in such a way that the majority of people no
longer live within walking distance of their place of employment, shopping
areas and recreational opportuni ties, so that they HAVE TO depend on the
automobile for transportation. Or else they must use public transportation,
in which case they have even less control over their own movement than
when driving a car. Even the walker's freedom is now greatly restri cted.
In the city he continually has to stop and wait for traffic lights that
are designed mainly to serve auto traffic. In the country, motor traffic
makes it dangerous and unpleasant to walk along the highway. (Note the
important point we have illustrat ed with the case of motorized transport:
When a new item of technology is introduced as an option that an individual
can accept or not as he chooses, it does not necessarily REMAIN optional.
In many cases the new technology changes society in such a way t hat people
eventually find themselves FORCED to use it.)
128. While technological
progress AS A WHOLE continually narrows our sphere of freedom, each new
technical advance CONSIDERED BY ITSELF appears to be desirable. Electricity,
indoor plumbing, rapid long-distance communications . . . how could one
argue against any of these things, or against any other of the innumerable
technical advances that have made modern society? It would have been absurd
to resist the introduction of the telephone, for example. It offered many
advantages and no disadvantages. Yet as we explained in paragraphs 59-76,
all these technical advances taken together have created world in which
the average man's fate is no longer in his own hands or in the hands of
his neighbors and friends, but in those of politicians, corporation execu
tives and remote, anonymous technicians and bureaucrats whom he as an individual
has no power to influence. [21] The same process will continue in the future.
Take genetic engineering, for example. Few people will resist the introduction
of a genetic tech nique that eliminates a hereditary disease It does no
apparent harm and prevents much suffering. Yet a large number of genetic
improvements taken together will make the human being into an engineered
product rather than a free creation of chance (or of G od, or whatever,
depending on your religious beliefs).
129 Another reason why technology
is such a powerful social force is that, within the context of a given
society, technological progress marches in only one direction; it can never
be reversed. Once a technical innovation has been introduced, people us
ually become dependent on it, unless it is replaced by some still more
advanced innovation. Not only do people become dependent as individuals
on a new item of technology, but, even more, the system as a whole becomes
dependent on it. (Imagine what would happen to the system today if computers,
for example, were eliminated.) Thus the system can move in only one direction,
toward greater technologization. Technology repeatedly forces freedom to
take a step back -- short of the overthrow of the whole techno logical
system.
130. Technology advances
with great rapidity and threatens freedom at many different points at the
same time (crowding, rules and regulations, increasing dependence of individuals
on large organizations, propaganda and other psychological techniques,
g enetic engineering, invasion of privacy through surveillance devices
and computers, etc.) To hold back any ONE of the threats to freedom would
require a long different social struggle. Those who want to protect freedom
are overwhelmed by the sheer number of new attacks and the rapidity with
which they develop, hence they become pathetic and no longer resist. To
fight each of the threats separately would be futile. Success can be hoped
for only by fighting the technological system as a whole; but that is r
evolution not reform.
131. Technicians (we use
this term in its broad sense to describe all those who perform a specialized
task that requires training) tend to be so involved in their work (their
surrogate activity) that when a conflict arises between their technical
work and freedom, they almost always decide in favor of their technical
work. This is obvious in the case of scientists, but it also appears elsewhere:
Educators, humanitarian groups, conservation organizations do not hesitate
to use propaganda or other psycho logical techniques to help them achieve
their laudable ends. Corporations and government agencies, when they find
it useful, do not hesitate to collect information about individuals without
regard to their privacy. Law enforcement agencies are frequently inconvenienced
by the constitutional rights of suspects and often of completely innocent
persons, and they do whatever they can do legally (or sometimes illegally)
to restrict or circumvent those rights. Most of these educators, government
officials and l aw officers believe in freedom, privacy and constitutional
rights, but when these conflict with their work, they usually feel that
their work is more important.
132. It is well known that
people generally work better and more persistently when striving for a
reward than when attempting to avoid a punishment or negative outcome.
Scientists and other technicians are motivated mainly by the rewards they
get throu gh their work. But those who oppose technilogiccal invasions
of freedom are working to avoid a negative outcome, consequently there
are a few who work persistently and well at this discouraging task. If
reformers ever achieved a signal victory that seemed to set up a solid
barrier against further erosion of freedom through technological progress,
most would tend to relax and turn their attention to more agreeable pursuits.
But the scientists would remain busy in their laboratories, and technology
as it pr ogresses would find ways, in spite of any barriers, to exert more
and more control over individuals and make them always more dependent on
the system.
133. No social arrangements,
whether laws, institutions, customs or ethical codes, can provide permanent
protection against technology. History shows that all social arrangements
are transitory; they all change or break down eventually. But technologic
al advances are permanent within the context of a given civilization. Suppose
for example that it were possible to arrive at some social arrangements
that would prevent genetic engineering from being applied to human beings,
or prevent it from being appli ed in such a ways as to threaten freedom
and dignity. Still, the technology would remain waiting. Sooner or later
the social arrangement would break down. Probably sooner, given that pace
of change in our society. Then genetic engineering would begin to i nvade
our sphere of freedom, and this invasion would be irreversible (short of
a breakdown of technological civilization itself). Any illusions about
achieving anything permanent through social arrangements should be dispelled
by what is currently happeni ng with environmental legislation. A few years
ago it seemed that there were secure legal barriers preventing at least
SOME of the worst forms of environmental degradation. A change in the political
wind, and those barriers begin to crumble.
134. For all of the foregoing
reasons, technology is a more powerful social force than the aspiration
for freedom. But this statement requires an important qualification. It
appears that during the next several decades the industrial-technological
syst em will be undergoing severe stresses due to economic and environmental
problems, and especially due to problems of human behavior (alienation,
rebellion, hostility, a variety of social and psychological difficulties).
We hope that the stresses through wh ich the system is likely to pass will
cause it to break down, or at least weaken it sufficiently so that a revolution
occurs and is successful, then at that particular moment the aspiration
for freedom will have proved more powerful than technology.
135. In paragraph 125 we
used an analogy of a weak neighbor who is left destitute by a strong neighbor
who takes all his land by forcing on him a series of compromises. But suppose
now that the strong neighbor gets sick, so that he is unable to defend
himself. The weak neighbor can force the strong one to give him his land
back, or he can kill him. If he lets the strong man survive and only forces
him to give his land back, he is a fool, because when the strong man gets
well he will again take all the land for himself. The only sensible alternative
for the weaker man is to kill the strong one while he has the chance. In
the same way, while the industrial system is sick we must destroy it. If
we compromise with it and let it recover from its sickness, i t will eventually
wipe out all of our freedom.
SIMPLER SOCIAL PROBLEMS HAVE
PROVED INTRACTABLE
136. If anyone still imagines
that it would be possible to reform the system in such a way as to protect
freedom from technology, let him consider how clumsily and for the most
part unsuccessfully our society has dealt with other social problems that
a re far more simple and straightforward. Among other things, the system
has failed to stop environmental degradation, political corruption, drug
trafficking or domestic abuse.
137. Take our environmental
problems, for example. Here the conflict of values is straightforward:
economic expedience now versus saving some of our natural resources for
our grandchildren [22] But on this subject we get only a lot of blather
and obfus cation from the people who have power, and nothing like a clear,
consistent line of action, and we keep on piling up environmental problems
that our grandchildren will have to live with. Attempts to resolve the
environmental issue consist of struggles and compromises between different
factions, some of which are ascendant at one moment, others at another
moment. The line of struggle changes with the shifting currents of public
opinion. This is not a rational process, or is it one that is likely to
lead to a timely and successful solution to the problem. Major social problems,
if they get "solved" at all, are rarely or never solved through any rational,
comprehensive plan. They just work themselves out through a process in
which various competing groups pu rsing their own usually short-term) self-interest
[23] arrive (mainly by luck) at some more or less stable modus vivendi.
In fact, the principles we formulated in paragraphs 100-106 make it seem
doubtful that rational, long-term social planning can EVER b e successful.
138. Thus it is clear that the human race has at best a very limited capacity
for solving even relatively straightforward social problems. How then is
it going to solve the far more difficult and subtle problem of reconciling
freedom with technology? Te chnology presents clear-cut material advantages,
whereas freedom is an abstraction that means different things to different
people, and its loss is easily obscured by propaganda and fancy talk.
139. And note this important
difference: It is conceivab le that our environmental problems (for example)
may some day be settled through a rational, comprehensive plan, but if
this happens it will be only because it is in the long-term interest of
the system to solve these problems. But it is NOT in the inter est of the
system to preserve freedom or small-group autonomy. On the contrary, it
is in the interest of the system to bring human behavior under control
to the greatest possible extent. <24> Thus, while practical considerations
may eventually force the s ystem to take a rational, prudent approach to
environmental problems, equally practical considerations will force the
system to regulate human behavior ever more closely (preferably by indirect
means that will disguise the encroachment on freedom.) This isn't just
our opinion. Eminent social scientists (e.g. James Q. Wilson) have stressed
the importance of "socializing" people more effectively.
REVOLUTION IS EASIER THAN REFORM
140. We hope we have convinced
the reader that the system cannot be reformed in a such a way as to reconcile
freedom with technology. The only way out is to dispense with the industrial-tech
nological system altogether. This implies revolution, not necessarily an
armed uprising, but certainly a radical and fundamental change in the nature
of society.
141. People tend to assume
that because a revolution involves a much greater change than reform does,
it is more difficult to bring about than reform is. Actually, under certain
circumstances revolution is much easier than reform. The reason is that
a revolutionary movement can inspire an intensity of commitment that a
reform movement cann ot inspire. A reform movement merely offers to solve
a particular social problem A revolutionary movement offers to solve all
problems at one stroke and create a whole new world; it provides the kind
of ideal for which people will take great risks and ma ke great sacrifices.
For this reasons it would be much easier to overthrow the whole technological
system than to put effective, permanent restraints on the development of
application of any one segment of technology, such as genetic engineering,
but unde r suitable conditions large numbers of people may devote themselves
passionately to a revolution against the industrial-technological system.
As we noted in paragraph 132, reformers seeking to limite certain aspects
of technology would be working to avoid a negative outcome. But revolutionaries
work to gain a powerful reward -- fulfillment of their revolutionary vision
-- and therefore work harder and more persistently than reformers do.
142. Reform is always restrainde
by the fear of painful conseque nces if changes go too far. But once a
revolutionary fever has taken hold of a society, people are willing to
undergo unlimited hardships for the sake of their revolution. This was
clearly shown in the French and Russian Revolutions. It may be that in
su ch cases only a minority of the population is really committed to the
revolution, but this minority is sufficiently large and active so that
it becomes the dominant force in society. We will have more to say about
revolution in paragraphs 180-205.
CONTROL OF HUMAN BEHAVIOR
143. Since the beginning of
civilization, organized societies have had to put pressures on human beings
of the sake of the functioning of the social organism. The kinds of pressures
vary greatly from on e society to another. Some of the pressures are physical
(poor diet, excessive labor, environmental pollution), some are psychological
(noise, crowding, forcing humans behavior into the mold that society requires).
In the past, human nature has been appro ximately constant, or at any rate
has varied only within certain bounds. Consequently, societies have been
able to push people only up to certain limits. When the limit of human
endurance has been passed, things start going rong: rebellion, or crime,
or c orruption, or evasion of work, or depression and other mental problems,
or an elevated death rate, or a declining birth rate or something else,
so that either the society breaks down, or its functioning becomes too
inefficient and it is (quickly or gradua lly, through conquest, attrition
or evolution) replaces by some more efficient form of society.
[25]
144. Thus human nature has
in the past put certain limits on the development of societies. People
coud be pushed only so far and no farther. But to day this may be changing,
because modern technology is developing way of modifying human beings.
145. Imagine a society
that subjects people to conditions that amke them terribley unhappy, then
gives them the drugs to take away their unhappiness. Scien ce fiction?
It is already happening to some extent in our own society. It is well known
that the rate of clinical depression had been greatly increasing in recent
decades. We believe that this is due to disruption fo the power process,
as explained in par agraphs 59-76. But even if we are wrong, the increasing
rate of depression is certainly the result of SOME conditions that exist
in today's society. Instead of removing the conditions that make people
depressed, modern society gives them antidepressant dr ugs. In effect,
antidepressants area a means of modifying an individual's internal state
in such a way as to enable him to toelrate social conditions that he would
otherwise find intolerable. (Yes, we know that depression is often of purely
genetic origin . We are referring here to those cases in which environment
plays the predominant role.)
146. Drugs that affect the
mind are only one example of the methods of controlling human behavior
that modern society is developing. Let us look at some of the ot her methods.
147. To start with, there
are the techniques of surveillance. Hidden video cameras are now used in
most stores and in many other places, computers are used to collect and
process vast amounts of information about individuals. Information so obtained
greatly increases the effectiveness of physical coercion (i.e., law enforcement).[26]
Then there are the methods of propaganda, for which the mass communication
media provide effective vehicles. Efficient techniques have been developed
for win ning elections, selling products, influencing public opinion. The
entertainment industry serves as an important psychological tool of the
system, possibly even when it is dishing out large amounts of sex and violence.
Entertainment provides modern man wi th an essential means of escape. While
absorbed in television, videos, etc., he can forget stress, anxiety, frustration,
dissatisfaction. Many primitive peoples, when they don't have work to do,
are quite content to sit for hours at a time doing nothing a t all, because
they are at peace with themselves and their world. But most modern people
must be contantly occupied or entertained, otherwise the get "bored," i.e.,
they get fidgety, uneasy, irritable.
148. Other techniques strike
deeper that the fore going. Education is no longer a simple affair of paddling
a kid's behind when he doesn't know his lessons and patting him on the
head when he does know them. It is becoming a scientific technique for
controlling the child's development. Sylvan Learning Ce nters, for example,
have had great success in motivating children to study, and psychological
techniques are also used with more or less success in many conventional
schools. "Parenting" techniques that are taught to parents are designed
to make children accept fundamental values of the system and behave in
ways that the system finds desirable. "Mental health" programs, "intervention"
techniques, psychotherapy and so forth are ostensibly designed to benefit
individuals, but in practice they usually serve as methods for inducing
individuals to think and behave as the system requires. (There is no contradiction
here; an individual whose attitudes or behavior bring him into conflict
with the system is up against a force that is too powerful for him to conque
r or escape from, hence he is likely to suffer from stress, frustration,
defeat. His path will be much easier if he thinks and behaves as the system
requires. In that sense the system is acting for the benefit of the individual
when it brainwashes him int o conformity.) Child abuse in its gross and
obvious forms is disapproved in most if not all cultures. Tormenting a
child for a trivial reason or no reason at all is something that appalls
almost everyone. But many psychologists interpret the concept of ab use
much more broadly. Is spanking, when used as part of a rational and consistent
system of discipline, a form of abuse? The question will ultimately be
decided by whether or not spanking tends to produce behavior that makes
a person fit in well with the existing system of society. In practice,
the word "abuse" tends to be interpreted to include any method of child-rearing
that produces behavior inconvenient for the system. Thus, when they go
beyond the prevention of obvious, senseless cruelty, programs for preventing
"child abuse" are directed toward the control of human behavior of the
system.
149. Presumably, research
will continue to increas the effectiveness of psychological techniques
for controlling human behavior. But we think it is unlikely that psychological
techniques alone will be sufficient to adjust human beings to the kind
of society that technology is creating. Biological methods probably will
have to be used. We have already mentiond the use of drugs in this connection.
Neurology may provide other avenues of modifying the human mind. Genetic
engineering of human beings is already beginning to occur in the form of
"gene therapy," and there is no reason to assume the such methods will
not eventually be used to modify those aspects of t he body that affect
mental funtioning.
150. As we mentioned in
paragraph 134, industrial society seems likely to be entering a period
of severe stress, due in part to problems of human behavior and in part
to economic and environmental problems. And a considerable proportion of
the system's economic and environmental problems result from the way human
beings behave. Alienation, low self-esteem, depression, hostility, rebellion;
children who won't study, youth gangs, illegal drug use, rape, child abuse
, other crimes, unsafe sex, teen pregnancy, population growth, political
corruption, race hatred, ethnic rivalry, bitter ideological conflict (i.e.,
pro-choice vs. pro-life), political extremism, terrorism, sabotage, anti-government
groups, hate groups. A ll these threaten the very survival of the system.
The system will be FORCED to use every practical means of controlling human
behavior.
151. The social disruption
that we see today is certainly not the result of mere chance. It can only
be a result f o the conditions of life that the system imposes on people.
(We have argued that the most important of these conditions is disruption
of the power process.) If the systems succeeds in imposing sufficient control
over human behavior to assure itw own survi val, a new watershed in human
history will have passed. Whereas formerly the limits of human endurance
have imposed limits on the development of societies (as we explained in
paragraphs 143, 144), industrial-technological society will be able to
pass thos e limits by modifying human beings, whether by psychological
methods or biological methods or both. In the future, social systems will
not be adjusted to suit the needs of human beings. Instead, human being
will be adjusted to suit the needs of the system .
[27] 152. Generally
speaking, technological control over human behavior will probably not be
introduced with a totalitarian intention or even through a conscious desire
to restrict human freedom. [28] Each new step in the assertion of control
over th e human mind will be taken as a rational response to a problem
that faces society, such as curing alcoholism, reducing the crime rate
or inducing young people to study science and engineering. In many cases,
there will be humanitarian justification. For e xample, when a psychiatrist
prescribes an anti-depressant for a depressed patient, he is clearly doing
that individual a favor. It would be inhumane to withhold the drug from
someone who needs it. When parents send their children to Sylvan Learning
Center s to have them manipulated into becoming enthusiastic about their
studies, they do so from concern for their children's welfare. It may be
that some of these parents wish that one didn't have to have specialized
training to get a job and that their kid di dn't have to be brainwashed
into becoming a computer nerd. But what can they do? They can't change
society, and their child may be unemployable if he doesn't have certain
skills. So they send him to Sylvan.
153. Thus control over human
behavior will b e introduced not by a calculated decision of the authorities
but through a process of social evolution (RAPID evolution, however). The
process will be impossible to resist, because each advance, considered
by itself, will appear to be beneficial, or at le ast the evil involved
in making the advance will appear to be beneficial, or at least the evil
involved in making the advance will seem to be less than that which would
result from not making it (see paragraph 127). Propaganda for example is
used for many good purposes, such as discouraging child abuse or race hatred.
[14] Sex education is obviously useful, yet the effect of sex education
(to the extent that it is successful) is to take the shaping of sexual
attitudes away from the family and put it into the hands of the state as
represented by the public school system.
154. Suppose a biological
trait is discovered that increases the likelihood that a child will grow
up to be a criminal and suppose some sort of gene therapy can remove this
trait. [29] Of course most parents whose children possess the trait will
have them undergo the therapy. It would be inhumane to do otherwise, since
the child would probably have a miserable life if he grew up to be a criminal.
But many or most primitive societies ha ve a low crime rate in comparison
with that of our society, even though they have neither high-tech methods
of child-rearing nor harsh systems of punishment. Since there is no reason
to suppose that more modern men than primitive men have innate predatory
tendencies, the high crime rate of our society must be due to the pressures
that modern conditions put on people, to which many cannot or will not
adjust. Thus a treatment designed to remove potential criminal tendencies
is at least in part a way of re-e ngineering people so that they suit the
requirements of the system.
155. Our society tends to
regard as a "sickness" any mode of thought or behavior that is inconvenient
for the system, and this is plausible because when an individual doesn't
fit into the system it causes pain to the individual as well as problems
for the system. Thus the manipulation of an individual to adjust him to
the system is seen as a "cure" for a "sickness" and therefore as good.
156. In paragraph 127 we
pointed out that i f the use of a new item of technology is INITIALLY optional,
it does not necessarily REMAIN optional, because the new technology tends
to change society in such a way that it becomes difficult or impossible
for an individual to function without using that technology. This applies
also to the technology of human behavior. In a world in which most children
are put through a program to make them enthusiastic about studying, a parent
will almost be forced to put his kid through such a program, because if
he d oes not, then the kid will grow up to be, comparatively speaking,
an ignoramus and therefore unemployable. Or suppose a biological treatment
is discovered that, without undesirable side-effects, will greatly reduce
the psychological stress from which so m any people suffer in our society.
If large numbers of people choose to undergo the treatment, then the general
level of stress in society will be reduced, so that it will be possible
for the system to increase the stress-producing pressures. In fact, some
thing like this seems to have happened already with one of our society's
most important psychological tools for enabling people to reduce (or at
least temporarily escape from) stress, namely, mass entertainment (see
paragraph 147). Our use of mass enterta inment is "optional": No law requires
us to watch television, listen to the radio, read magazines. Yet mass entertainment
is a means of escape and stress-reduction on which most of us have become
dependent. Everyone complains about the trashiness of telev ision, but
almost everyone watches it. A few have kicked the TV habit, but it would
be a rare person who could get along today without using ANY form of mass
entertainment. (Yet until quite recently in human history most people got
along very nicely with no other entertainment than that which each local
community created for itself.) Without the entertainment industry the system
probably would not have been able to get away with putting as much stress-producing
pressure on us as it does.
157. Assuming that industrial
society survives, it is likely that technology will eventually acquire
something approaching complete control over human behavior. It has been
established beyond any rational doubt that human thought and behavior have
a largely biological basis. As experimenters have demonstrated, feelings
such as hunger, pleasure, anger and fear can be turned on and off by electrical
stimulation of appropriate parts of the brain. Memories can be destroyed
by damaging parts of the brain or they can be bro ught to the surface by
electrical stimulation. Hallucinations can be induced or moods changed
by drugs. There may or may not be an immaterial human soul, but if there
is one it clearly is less powerful that the biological mechanisms of human
behavior. For if that were not the case then researchers would not be able
so easily to manipulate human feelings and behavior with drugs and electrical
currents.
158. It presumably would
be impractical for all people to have electrodes inserted in their heads
so that they could be controlled by the authorities. But the fact that
human thoughts and feelings are so open to biological intervention shows
that the problem of controlling human behavior is mainly a technical problem;
a problem of neurons, hormones and c omplex molecules; the kind of problem
that is accessible to scientific attack. Given the outstanding record of
our society in solving technical problems, it is overwhelmingly probable
that great advances will be made in the control of human behavior.
159. Will public resistance
prevent the introduction of technological control of human behavior? It
certainly would if an attempt were made to introduce such control all at
once. But since technological control will be introduced through a long
sequence o f small advances, there will be no rational and effective public
resistance. (See paragraphs 127,132, 153.)
160. To those who think
that all this sounds like science fiction, we point out that yesterday's
science fiction is today's fact. The Industrial Revolution has radically
altered man's environment and way of life, and it is only to be expected
that as technology is increasingly applied to the human body and mind,
man himself will be altered as radically as his environment and way of
life have been. |